Abstract
As Jonathan
Barnes has reflected along with Hugh Lloyd-Jones and David Lachterman among others
in an older tradition, including Karl Reinhardt and, most recently, as Gherardo
Ugolini and, in the broader tradition of philology, as Christian Benne has
argued, it is worth questioning the convention that Nietzsche was ‘not really’ a
classical philologist. Yet scholarly reception of Nietzsche continues to be
conducted (even for exceptions such James Porter, Glenn Most, John Hamilton, even
André Laks) on the same terms that informed Wilamowitz’ juvenile critique. As
Nietzsche reproaches himself in his own “Versuch
einer Selbstkritik” written to accompany the republication (unaltered) of
his first book, the “ears” for his reading of antiquity seem not to have
existed — as they do not seem to exist today.
Of the Preplatonic thinkers Nietzsche writes: “It is a veritable misfortune that we have so little extant of the works
of the ancient masters and that not a single one of their works was handed down
to us complete.” For Nietzsche, we cannot
but err: offering scholarly judgments rather as one searches for one’s keys
under the lamp-post owing more to the sheer abundance of light than for any
likelihood of finding them in just that spot, ranking “with false standards,
letting ourselves be disposed more favorably toward Plato and Aristotle by the
sheer accident that they never lacked connoisseurs and copyists.” This happenstance
inclines us to measure the rest of philosophy by their standards, unideal given
their own efforts to eclipse those aspects of the past not seeming to culminate
in themselves.
Nietzsche’s
hermeneutic emphasis highlights the difference between our tastes (what seems
right to us) by contrast with the effort to read the ancients on their own
terms: “what philosophy was for them.” By describing Plato as a “mix’t type,” utterly
“unoriginal,” Nietzsche emphasizes the purity of thinkers before him such that philosophy
in Greek antiquity is not estranged from itself whereas, beginning with Plato, philosophy
goes into self-exile. Thus Nietzsche’s
reading of such ‘Preplatonics’ (hence including Socrates) by contrast with those
Diels traditionally names the ‘Presocratics’ yields a range of useful insights
beginning with a radical liberation from the Aristotelian-cum-Hegelian
strictures of the doxographic tradition and not less the opportunity for
critical historiography.
Most
informative can be Nietzsche’s proto-structuralist hermeneutics of the tripod (coincidentally
relevant as we find ourselves in Delphi), his discussion of the ‘person’ (Homer,
Archilochus) and his reading of Anaximander (as ethical thinker) and perhaps his
(to this day still) pathbreaking discussion of Anaxagoras as leading Athenian
philosopher [Hauptphilosoph] foregrounding
his noble traits (especially for Pericles), and not less as model for Aristophanes’
Socrates, and, arguably, for Plato’s cosmology as such. Also of interest is the
divine or useless character of philosophy and a reflection on Die mythische Vorstufe der Philosophie.
Key
words: Preplatonics, διαδοχή, personality, historiography,
Anaxagoras, uselessness
Comments
Post a Comment